Skip to main content

Voluntary stopping of eating and drinking: is medical support ethically justified?

A Commentary to this article was published on 20 October 2017

Abstract

Background

Physician-assisted dying has been the subject of extensive discussion and legislative activity both in Europe and North America. In this context, dying by voluntary stopping of eating and drinking (VSED) is often proposed, and practiced, as an alternative method of self-determined dying, with medical support for VSED being regarded as ethically and legally justified.

Argument

In our opinion, this view is flawed. First, we argue that VSED falls within the concept of suicide, albeit with certain unique features (non-invasiveness, initial reversibility, resemblance to the natural dying process). Second, we demonstrate, on the basis of paradigmatic clinical cases, that medically supported VSED is, at least in some instances, tantamount to assisted suicide. This is especially the case if a patient’s choice of VSED depends on the physician’s assurance to provide medical support.

Conclusion

Thus, for many jurisdictions worldwide, medically supported VSED may fall within the legal prohibitions on suicide assistance. Physicians, lawmakers, and societies should discuss specific ways of regulating medical support for VSED in order to provide clear guidance for both patients and healthcare professionals.

Please see related article: http://bmcmedicine.biomedcentral.com/articles/10.1186/s12916-017-0951-0.

Peer Review reports

Background

Severely ill patients with a short life expectancy may have the desire to hasten death [1, 2]. Yet, euthanasia and assisted suicide (together called ‘assisted dying’) are legally prohibited in most countries, despite a recent liberalization in some North American jurisdictions [3, 4]. Therefore, patients may resort to another option to hasten their death – voluntary stopping of eating and drinking (VSED) [5] – wherein patients deliberately and voluntarily cease eating and/or drinking to bring about their own death earlier than it would have occurred naturally [6]. Studies show that the prevalence of VSED is underestimated and may in fact be higher than that of assisted suicide [7, 8]. Although the dying process is generally reported to be peaceful, symptoms such as thirst, pain, insomnia, anxiety, and delirium may require medical support [7,8,9]. Professional medical organizations, while rejecting assisted dying, are increasingly advocating VSED (and medical support for VSED) without giving a convincing ethical justification [10,11,12]. Most Western jurisdictions seem to permit medical support for VSED [13], even in jurisdictions where assisted dying is prohibited by law, such as England and (partially) Germany [14, 15]. However, a clear legal basis for medically supported VSED in statute or common law is often lacking. Indeed, healthcare professionals often express moral uncertainty as to whether medical support in the context of VSED constitutes suicide assistance [16].

In this article, we first show that VSED should be categorized, on a purely descriptive basis, as a form of suicide, albeit with particular characteristics that are not shared by other forms. Second, we argue that supporting patients who embark on VSED amounts to assistance in suicide, at least in some instances, depending on the kind of support and its relation to the patient’s intention. Third, we conclude that, given the ethical equivalence of supported VSED and assisted suicide in some cases, consistency is required in either allowing or restricting both forms of aid in dying, depending on the normative grounds for justification. This will have significant repercussions for the ethics codes of the medical profession as well as the law in several jurisdictions.

Argument

VSED and suicide

In colloquial language, suicide is understood as the act of intentionally taking one’s own life [17]. Legal definitions usually focus on the action, the intention, and the decision-making capacity, as indicated by the definition in Black’s Law Dictionary: “Suicide is the willful and voluntary act of a person who understands the physical nature of the act, and intends by it to accomplish the result of self-destruction” [18]. For the purpose of this article, two elements in these definitions deserve scrutiny – the action and the intention.

First, there has to be an action initiated by the patient to cause the own death. Causation is understood in the common legal way, comprising the necessary condition (factual cause) and the sufficient condition (proximate cause) for death to occur [19]. As such, suicide is different from dying through withdrawing and withholding of life-sustaining treatment. If, for example, artificial ventilation is stopped, this may be a necessary condition for dying, but certainly not a sufficient condition, because there has to be a respiratory pathology incompatible with life that exerts its life-terminating effect once ventilation (having temporarily suspended this effect) has been withdrawn.

The suicidal action that causes death does not have to be a positive act; it may also be an omission. It is firmly established in philosophy and law that both acts and omissions can be employed intentionally to cause certain states of affairs and can thus be regarded as forms of human agency [20]. While the most frequent forms of suicide involve positive acts (e.g., gunshot, drug overdose, hanging, and so on), there are also undisputed forms of suicide by omission. Suicidal persons may seek life-threatening situations (e.g., in traffic, water, skydiving) and deliberately refrain from rescuing themselves, even though they could easily do so. If we apply this concept of suicide to VSED, it becomes evident that VSED is a form of suicide by omission [21] – the person’s omission of eating and drinking directly causes death. The cessation of the physiological influx of nutrients and water in VSED parallels the cessation of the physiological influx of oxygen that occurs in hanging or drowning. By contrast, when withdrawing artificial nutrition, hydration, or ventilation, it is not a physiological everyday behavior that is stopped but a medical treatment that technically replaces a pathologically lost organ function.

The second element of suicide that becomes evident in the abovementioned definitions is the intention to kill oneself. This does not mean the intention to allow death to occur naturally (as is the case in withdrawing life-sustaining treatment), but the intention to hasten one’s death. In VSED, the latter intention is clearly present. First, this intention is usually verbalized by the patient towards family members and healthcare professionals [7, 8]. Second, the intention to hasten death is impressively demonstrated by the patient’s resolve to endure hunger and thirst in order to reach this goal. Intention is also the key element that distinguishes VSED as a form of suicide from the alleviation of pain and symptoms with a possible life-shortening effect (sometimes called ‘indirect euthanasia’), which is not a form of suicide. In the latter, patients accept the possibility of a life-shortening effect of high-dosed drugs that are required to treat otherwise uncontrollable symptoms in the dying phase. Irrespective of whether the shortening of life may be a contingent side effect or a necessary means to symptom control, the primary intention is always symptom relief and not death.

VSED should therefore be considered as a form of suicide, as there is both an intention to bring about death and an omission that directly causes this effect. However, there are some characteristics that render VSED a discrete form of suicide, distinct from other forms. Firstly, in contrast to common forms of suicide (e.g., use of firearms, hanging or suffocation, poisoning, falling) [22], VSED is not characterized by an invasive or aggressive act. Second, other methods of suicide typically result in a relatively rapid death, occurring within seconds to minutes, whereas even a complete cessation of eating and drinking will only lead to death after at least several days. As a consequence, the decision to kill oneself can be reversed by resuming eating and drinking [23], at least up to a certain point of no return when the patient loses consciousness or when organ damage is too advanced to save the patient’s life. Moreover, this protracted course and the suffering that may accompany it require more resolve from the patient than quicker forms of suicide, thus providing a better safeguard against impulsive suicidal behavior. Finally, phenomenologically, the dying phase in VSED resembles that of the natural dying process, which also involves some degree of dehydration. This may be a significant advantage for patients as well as relatives and healthcare professionals and may partly explain the widespread acceptance of this practice.

Whilst these three particular characteristics of VSED do not change its status as a form of suicide, they may have an impact on its ethical evaluation. Although suicide is not generally seen as immoral behavior, some features of the various forms of suicide may render them more or less ethically acceptable. For example, jumping in front of a moving train and traumatizing the driver may provoke moral reproach, whereas dying by VSED is not directly harmful to others (although the stress imparted on the relatives by the patient’s protracted death may be significant).

VSED support and suicide assistance

The question now emerges as to whether the various kinds of support that patients receive in the context of VSED equal to assistance in suicide. In those regions where assisted suicide is, under certain conditions, lawful (e.g., in Switzerland, Oregon, and Washington State), a healthcare professional, family member, or right-to-die association organizes and provides a lethal drug for the patient to swallow or, in the case of swallowing difficulties, an infusion that the patient can deliberately initiate. Two elements of assistance in suicide are critical for our argumentation. First, the assistance is instrumental for death to occur, meaning that, without the assistance, the suicide would not (or could not) occur. Second, the assisting person knows and at least partially shares the patient’s intention to induce death. These two elements are critical when evaluating the medical support that patients can receive in the context of VSED. Four paradigmatic types of scenarios can thus be distinguished:

  1. A.

    The physician suggests VSED as a way of dying when the patient was unaware of this possibility or did not contemplate it (encouragement).

  2. B.

    The physician promises to provide symptom relief or any other kind of support after stopping eating and drinking and the patient would choose this way of dying only because of having received this promise beforehand (promise).

  3. C.

    The patient has already stopped eating and drinking, but would resume oral intake and stop the suicidal process due to suffering if symptom relief or other kinds of support were not provided (support to continue).

  4. D.

    The patient has stopped eating and drinking and is in need of symptom relief (e.g., because of pain or delirium) or other kinds of medical support but will continue refraining from eating and drinking irrespective of whether this support is provided or not (decision-unrelated support).

Ethically, scenarios A–C differ significantly from scenario D (Fig. 1). In the first three cases, physician support is instrumental to suicide, i.e., support is a necessary condition without which suicide would not occur. It is of secondary importance whether the condition is objectively necessary for suicide to occur, as in scenario A, or subjectively necessary (from a patient’s perspective), as in scenarios B and C. Moreover, in scenarios A–C, physicians know and at least partially share a patient’s intention to hasten death by VSED. In the encouragement case (scenario A), it is evident that physicians would not address the possibility of VSED if they were not prepared to endorse a patient’s intention to choose this option. In scenarios B (promise) and C (support to continue), physicians know that there is a real alternative to providing medical support, namely not embarking on VSED in scenario B or resuming eating and drinking in scenario C. Thus, in scenarios A-C, physicians need to at least partially share a patient’s intention in order to facilitate medically supported VSED. These two elements, instrumental agency and shared intention, imply physician ethical co-responsibility for VSED.

Fig. 1
figure 1

Medically supported voluntary stopping of eating and drinking (VSED): distinction of two ethically divergent types. Scenarios A–C and D are described in the text. † signifies death

However, in scenario D (decision-unrelated support), physician support is not instrumental to suicide (Fig. 1), because the patient would go ahead anyway. In addition, physicians may well have the sole intention to ease patient suffering and do not have to share the intention to hasten death. Physicians know that, given a patient’s resolve to continue with VSED in any case, there is no real alternative method to ease suffering other than to provide medical support. In contrast to scenario C, this support will not reinforce the decision for VSED and, as such, need not condone a patient’s intention to hasten death.

Thus, there are realistic scenarios (A–C; encouragement, promise, support to continue) in which medical support in the context of VSED fulfils the two critical conditions of suicide assistance, namely sharing the patient’s intention to hasten death and the instrumental nature of the medical act for the initiation or completion of the suicidal act. However, medical support that does not concern VSED but rather the withdrawing or withholding of life-sustaining treatment obviously does not constitute assistance in suicide as treatment limitation is distinct from suicide.

Conclusions

We have shown that VSED should be regarded as a discrete form of suicide and that medical support in the context of VSED can be equivalent to suicide assistance, depending on the form of support and its relation to the patient’s decision. Our analysis does not presuppose any ethical stance towards the legitimacy of VSED and medical support during VSED – both depend largely on the ethical legitimacy of suicide and suicide assistance, whose discussion is beyond the scope of this article [24, 25]. We do maintain, however, that future ethical discussions on assisted suicide require consideration of medically supported VSED, and vice versa [26].

Thus, the widely held position by palliative care societies, professional bodies of physicians, legal scholars, and ethicists to disapprove of assisted suicide but approve of and even promote medically supported VSED appears inconsistent [11, 12, 25, 27]. With the exception of one situational scenario, both end-of-life decisions should be jointly regarded as being either ethically legitimate or illegitimate. From a legal perspective, those jurisdictions that have legalized assisted suicide under certain procedural requirements may need to apply the same procedural rules to medically supported VSED. Simultaneously, all jurisdictions with laws prohibiting suicide assistance should apply the same laws to medically supported VSED, introduce specific legal regulations pertaining to VSED, or at the very least clarify the legal basis for medically supported VSED. Professional societies in healthcare should strive to harmonize their policies concerning assisted suicide and medically supported VSED. Regardless of their ethical stance, they should all promote a critical, evidence-based and transparent discussion on this clinically and ethically relevant issue.

Abbreviations

VSED:

Voluntary stopping of eating and drinking

References

  1. van der Heide A, Deliens L, Faisst K, Nilstun T, Norup M, Paci E, et al. End-of-life decision-making in six European countries: descriptive study. Lancet. 2003;362:345–50.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  2. Institute of Medicine. Dying in America: improving quality and honoring individual preferences near the end of life. Washington DC: National Academies Press; 2014.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Attaran A. Unanimity on death with dignity—legalizing physician-assisted dying in Canada. N Engl J Med. 2015;372:2080–2.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  4. Mishra R. Implementing California's law on assisted dying. Hastings Cent Rep. 2017;47:7–8.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  5. Berry ZS. Responding to suffering: providing options and respecting choice. J Pain Symptom Manage. 2009;38:797–800.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  6. Bernat JL, Gert B, Mogielnicki RP. Patient refusal of hydration and nutrition. An alternative to physician-assisted suicide or voluntary active euthanasia. Arch Intern Med. 1993;153:2723–8.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  7. Chabot BE, Goedhart A. A survey of self-directed dying attended by proxies in the Dutch population. Soc Sci Med. 2009;68:1745–51.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  8. Ganzini L, Goy ER, Miller LL, Harvath TA, Jackson A, Delorit MA. Nurses' experiences with hospice patients who refuse food and fluids to hasten death. N Engl J Med. 2003;349:359–65.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  9. Bolt EE, Hagens M, Willems D, Onwuteaka-Philipsen BD. Primary care patients hastening death by voluntarily stopping eating and drinking. Ann Fam Med. 2015;13:421–8.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  10. Quill TE, Byock IR. Responding to intractable terminal suffering: the role of terminal sedation and voluntary refusal of food and fluids. ACP-ASIM End-of-Life Care Consensus Panel. American College of Physicians-American Society of Internal Medicine. Ann Intern Med. 2000;132:408–14.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  11. Radbruch L, Leget C, Bahr P, Muller-Busch C, Ellershaw J, de Conno F, Vanden Berghe P. Euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide: a white paper from the European Association for Palliative Care. Palliat Med. 2016;30:104–16.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  12. Radbruch L, De Lima L. International Association for Hospice and Palliative Care response regarding voluntary cessation of food and water. J Palliat Med. 2017;20:578–9.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  13. Pope TM, West A. Legal briefing: voluntarily stopping eating and drinking. J Clin Ethics. 2014;25:68–80.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  14. Right-to-die man Tony Nicklinson dead after refusing food. BBC News. 22 Aug 2012. http://www.bbc.com/news/uk-england-19341722. Accessed 7 Oct 2017.

  15. Simon A, Hoekstra NL. Care for patients who choose hastened death by voluntarily stopping of eating and drinking. Dtsch Med Wochenschr. 2015;140:1100–2.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  16. Hoekstra NL, Strack M, Simon A. Physicians attitudes on voluntary refusal of food and fluids to hasten death, results of an empirical study among 255 physicians. Z Palliativmed. 2015;16:68–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Suicide. Encyclopaedia Britannica. http://www.britannica.com/topic/suicide. Accessed 7 Oct 2017.

  18. What is suicide? Black's Law Dictionary, 2nd edition. http://thelawdictionary.org/suicide/. Accessed 7 Oct 2017.

  19. Honoré A. Causation in the Law. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2010. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/causation-law/. Accessed 7 Oct 2017.

  20. Clarke R. Omissions: agency, metaphysics, and responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2014.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  21. Birnbacher D. Is voluntarily stopping eating and drinking a form of suicide? Ethik Med. 2015;27:315–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Miller M, Azrael D, Barber C. Suicide mortality in the United States: the importance of attending to method in understanding population-level disparities in the burden of suicide. Annu Rev Public Health. 2012;33:393–408.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  23. Fewing R, Kirk TW, Meisel A. A fading decision. Hastings Cent Rep. 2014;44(3):14.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  24. Rady MY, Verheijde JL. Distress from voluntary refusal of food and fluids to hasten death: what is the role of continuous deep sedation? J Med Ethics. 2012;38:510–2.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  25. White B, Willmott L, Savulescu J. Voluntary palliated starvation: a lawful and ethical way to die? J Law Med. 2014;22:376–86.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  26. Jansen LA. Voluntary stopping of eating and drinking (VSED), physician-assisted suicide (PAS), or neither in the last stage of life? PAS: no; VSED: it depends. Ann Fam Med. 2015;13:410–1.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  27. Quill TE, Lo B, Brock DW. Palliative options of last resort: a comparison of voluntarily stopping eating and drinking, terminal sedation, physician-assisted suicide, and voluntary active euthanasia. JAMA. 1997;278:2099–104.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank Dorothee Wagner von Hoff for proofreading.

Funding

The work of IB and JA for this article was supported by the German Ministry for Education and Research within the Joint Programme for Neurodegenerative Disease Research (No. 01ED1402B). The sponsor had no role in the theoretical analysis or the writing of the article.

Availability of data and materials

Not applicable.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

All authors equally contributed to the conceptual analysis. RJJ drafted the text and IB, JA, and GDB revised it substantially. RJJ and IB have expertise in medical ethics and law; RJJ, JA, and GDB have expertise in clinical medicine, particularly in palliative care. All authors read and approved the final manuscript.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ralf J. Jox.

Ethics declarations

Ethics approval and consent to participate

Not applicable.

Consent for publication

Not applicable.

Competing interests

The authors declare that they have no competing interests.

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were made. The Creative Commons Public Domain Dedication waiver (http://creativecommons.org/publicdomain/zero/1.0/) applies to the data made available in this article, unless otherwise stated.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Jox, R.J., Black, I., Borasio, G.D. et al. Voluntary stopping of eating and drinking: is medical support ethically justified?. BMC Med 15, 186 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1186/s12916-017-0950-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1186/s12916-017-0950-1

Keywords