Skip to main content

Adaptive trials, efficiency, and ethics

The Original Article was published on 02 August 2019

Background

Adaptive clinical trials employ a class of study designs that take advantage of the accumulating state of evidence in a trial to make midstream modifications to the trial’s structure or parameters. Under the right conditions, adaptive trials can be more efficient than traditional, non-adaptive designs. For example, they can allow several hypotheses to be tested using the same infrastructure, or fewer participants to be enrolled to achieve the same level of statistical power. But what are some of these ‘right’ conditions that make adaptive trials more efficient? This is the question asked by Wason et al. [1], who are concerned that the methodological literature may have overstated some of the advantages of adaptive designs, and overlooked some of the disadvantages.

When are adaptive trials most useful?

Consider, for example, outcome-adaptive trials, in which the treatment arms or allocation ratios are modified based upon preliminary outcome data. Wason et al. observe that the potential gains in efficiency from these designs are only realizable if the preliminary, accumulating outcomes are (1) reliable predictors of the final outcomes, and (2) measured quickly, relative to the total, planned length of the trial. If the first of these conditions does not hold, then the trial may end up being misleading, because it has adapted to outcome data that are not, ultimately, informative. If the second condition does not hold, then the trial may be no more efficient than a non-adaptive design, because the data needed to modify the trial does not accumulate fast enough, relative to the speed of enrollment.

Beyond the methodological implications of adaptive trials, the article by Wason et al. also raises some interesting questions at the intersection of trial efficiency and ethics. The authors point out that some outcome-adaptive designs may be more attractive to patients, because as the trial evolves, it can minimize the number of patients allocated to intervention arms that are later found to be inferior. Difficulty in recruitment is one of the biggest reasons trials are terminated [2], and there is evidence to suggest that allocation to inferior treatment (e.g., a placebo arm) makes some patients more reluctant to participate in trials [3]. Therefore, if scientifically appropriate use of adaptive trials can also increase patients’ willingness to enroll, then – at least on its face – this looks like a clear win–win opportunity.

Lingering ethical tensions

On closer inspection, however, there are some ethical tensions lurking beneath the idea that adaptive trials are (or should be) more attractive to patients. One of these tensions stems from the principle of beneficence, which requires a trial to have a favorable balance of risks and benefits [4]. However, the benefits in this ethical calculus cannot be the direct benefits to the participants from the experimental interventions, because these benefits are precisely what is being tested. The risks and burdens on the trial participants must therefore be offset by the benefits to future patients. Accordingly, the informed consent process for adaptive trials must make this ethical foundation clear: even if allocation is weighted in favor of the better-performing arms in the study, it does not necessarily mean that participation in the adaptive (rather than non-adaptive) trial is more likely to provide a direct therapeutic benefit [5].

A second ethical tension stems from the principle of clinical equipoise, which demands a genuine uncertainty within the expert community about the relative therapeutic merits across all arms in a controlled trial [6]. Two consequences of clinical equipoise are most relevant here: (1) patients should not be exposed to anything less than competent care; and (2) patients should not be systematically disadvantaged by their participation in the trial.

On the one hand, adaptive trials that drop arms, such as the Multi-Arm, Multi-Stage (MAMS) design [7], seem to operationalize clinical equipoise in an intuitive way. As soon as it is known that an intervention arm is ineffective or inferior (i.e., the arm no longer satisfies the conditions of clinical equipoise), then it is dropped from the trial. However, for adaptive trials that weight allocation in favor of better-performing arms, the implications of equipoise are less intuitive. As long as there is (and should still be) uncertainty about which arm is truly better, then there is no reason to think that patients are benefitting more or less by ending up in one arm or the other. In other words, because every arm must be consistent with clinical equipoise, patients are not advantaged or disadvantaged by their allocation [8].

Conclusion

If the above analysis is correct, adaptive trials may not be the win–win opportunity that they first appear to be. Some of the reasons why adaptive trials seem more attractive for patients may be based on misconceptions about what makes clinical trials ethical. An ethical trial is one in which every patient—no matter their allocation—has their interests protected and can be assured of receiving competent care [9]. Therefore, the fact that an arm or the structure of a trial evolves over time should not be understood or advertised as offering an advantage to the participants. Instead, adaptive trials should be understood as offering advantages to the research system as a whole. In this respect, adaptive trials can still be a win-win. When used under the appropriate conditions, as Wason et al. help to elucidate, adaptive trials can resolve scientific uncertainties, while minimizing the total burden on patient populations.

Availability of data and materials

Not applicable.

References

  1. Wason JMS, Brocklehurst P, Yap C. When to keep it simple—adaptive designs are not always useful. BMC Med. 2019;17:152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Williams RJ, Tse T, DiPiazza K, Zarin DA. Terminated trials in the ClinicalTrials. gov results database: evaluation of availability of primary outcome data and reasons for termination. PLoS One. 2015;10(5):e0127242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Mills EJ, Seely D, Rachlis B, Griffith L, Wu P, Wilson K, et al. Barriers to participation in clinical trials of cancer: a meta-analysis and systematic review of patient-reported factors. Lancet Oncol. 2006;7(2):141–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research. The Belmont Report: Ethical principles and guidelines for the protection of human subjects of research. Washington, DC: Department of Health, Education and Welfare; 1979.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Hey SP, Kimmelman J. Are outcome-adaptive allocation trials ethical? Clin Trials. 2015;12(2):102–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Freedman B. Equipoise and the ethics of clinical research. N Engl J Med. 1987;317(3):141–5.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  7. Wason JM, Jaki T. Optimal design of multi-arm multi-stage trials. Stat Med. 2012;31(30):4269–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Hey SP, Weijer C, Taljaard M, Kesselheim AS. Research ethics for emerging trial designs: does equipoise need to adapt? BMJ. 2018;360:k226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Hey SP, London AJ, Weijer C, Rid A, Miller F. Is the concept of clinical equipoise still relevant to research? BMJ. 2017;359:j5787.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Not applicable.

Funding

SPH receives funding from Arnold Ventures. The funder had no role in the planning or writing of this manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

SPH wrote the manuscript, and read and approved the final version.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Spencer Phillips Hey.

Ethics declarations

Ethics approval and consent to participate

Not applicable.

Consent for publication

Not applicable

Competing interests

The author declares that he has no competing interests.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were made. The Creative Commons Public Domain Dedication waiver (http://creativecommons.org/publicdomain/zero/1.0/) applies to the data made available in this article, unless otherwise stated.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hey, S.P. Adaptive trials, efficiency, and ethics. BMC Med 17, 189 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1186/s12916-019-1437-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1186/s12916-019-1437-z

Keywords