Skip to main content

Heterogeneity in pragmatic randomised trials: sources and management

Abstract

Background

Pragmatic trials aim to generate evidence to directly inform patient, caregiver and health-system manager policies and decisions. Heterogeneity in patient characteristics contributes to heterogeneity in their response to the intervention. However, there are many other sources of heterogeneity in outcomes. Based on the expertise and judgements of the authors, we identify different sources of clinical and methodological heterogeneity, which translate into heterogeneity in patient responses—some we consider as desirable and some as undesirable. For each of them, we discuss and, using real-world trial examples, illustrate how heterogeneity should be managed over the whole course of the trial.

Main text

Heterogeneity in centres and patients should be welcomed rather than limited. Interventions can be flexible or tailored and control interventions are expected to reflect usual care, avoiding use of a placebo. Co-interventions should be allowed; adherence should not be enforced. All these elements introduce heterogeneity in interventions (experimental or control), which has to be welcomed because it mimics reality. Outcomes should be objective and possibly routinely collected; standardised assessment, blinding and adjudication should be avoided as much as possible because this is not how assessment would be done outside a trial setting. The statistical analysis strategy must be guided by the objective to inform decision-making, thus favouring the intention-to-treat principle. Pragmatic trials should consider including process analyses to inform an understanding of the trial results. Needed data to conduct these analyses should be collected unobtrusively. Finally, ethical principles must be respected, even though this may seem to conflict with goals of pragmatism; consent procedures could be incorporated in the flow of care.

Peer Review reports

Introduction

Heterogeneity refers to the general concept of variability. In clinical studies, we classically consider three different types of heterogeneity [1]: clinical heterogeneity or “variability in participants, interventions and outcomes”, methodological heterogeneity or “variability in study design and risk of bias” and statistical heterogeneity or “variability in the intervention effects being evaluated in different studies”. Here, we focus on clinical and methodological heterogeneity, limiting ourselves to within-trial heterogeneity.

In 1967, Daniel Schwartz and Joseph Lellouch developed the concepts of explanatory and pragmatic attitudes in randomised clinical trials [2]. The explanatory approach “aim[s] at understanding. It seeks to discover whether a difference exists between two treatments which are specified by strict and usually simple definitions.” In contrast, the pragmatic approach “aim[s] at decision. It seeks to answer the question—which of the two treatments should we prefer?” Pragmatic trials aim to generate evidence to inform decisions made by patients or participants, physicians or other providers and health-system managers or other policy-makers [3]. Thus, a pragmatic trial must reproduce as much as possible the circumstances—including heterogeneity—under which the assessed intervention would be used in usual care. Pragmatic trials may be individually randomised or cluster randomised [4]. A cluster randomised trial is a trial in which intact social units rather than individual participants are randomised [5]. The units can be clinical (e.g. practices, wards, caregivers) or not (e.g. schools, geographical areas, families).

Because a pragmatic trial is expected to emulate usual health care delivery in the target setting, it should mimic the heterogeneity in patient outcomes expected outside the trial context. As a consequence, when planning, conducting and analysing a trial, some forms of heterogeneity should be welcomed (because they contribute to the fact that the trial mimics the future reality), but others are undesirable (because they are induced by the trial context and are not expected to be encountered in the future reality). In this paper, we aimed to identify these desirable and undesirable sources of heterogeneity in pragmatic trials based on our opinion. For each of them, we also discuss and illustrate with examples how they should be handled in trial planning, conduct and analysis to help people conduct their trials in a way to support pragmatic aims. Our analysis is based on the expertise and judgements of the authors consisting of four senior biostatisticians, a bioethicist, and a pragmatic trialist, all with a long experience in randomised trials.

According to the Patient, Intervention, Comparison, Outcome and Setting (PICOS) framework, [6] the manuscript is structured in three sections: (1) patients and settings of included centres (P and S domains of the PICOS), (2) intervention and control (C and O domains of the PICOS), and (3) outcome (O domain of the PICOS)), to which we added a fourth section related to regulatory and ethical issues, which may also affect heterogeneity. Table 1 summarises sources of heterogeneity in pragmatic trials and Table 2 our recommendations for management.

Table 1 Sources of heterogeneity in pragmatic trials as compared to explanatory trials
Table 2 Authors’ recommendations for managing sources of heterogeneity in pragmatic trial design, conduct and analysis

Patients and setting of included centres

Trial planning: select typical centres

Centres involved in a pragmatic trial should be drawn from a similar range of patient care settings as those in the target population for which the designers intend the findings of the trial will apply [7]. If study centres are limited and highly selected, heterogeneity will be reduced and may no longer fit the target population. For instance, centres should not exclusively be university hospitals when the disease of interest is common, and patients are cared for in both community and university hospitals (e.g. NUTRIREA-2 trial [8], Table 3).

Table 3 NUTRIREA-2: enteral versus parenteral early nutrition in ventilated adults with shock

An option is to maximise the number and range of included centres, perhaps reducing the number of patients per centre. In trials conducted across a health system, it may even be possible to recruit centres in random sequence until the required sample size is reached, thereby vouchsafing representativeness of the available sample and thus applicability to the target population (e.g. IRIS trial [9], Table 4).

Table 4 IRIS: training program to increase identification of female victims of domestic violence

In a cluster randomised trial, heterogeneity in selected centres has two further consequences. First, more variability in outcome between centres increases the intraclass correlation coefficient, and as a result, a larger sample size is required. Second, variability in cluster (centre) size also increases the required total sample size [10].

Finally, although differences in patient characteristics between centres may reflect a different patient case-mix between centres [11], which is a welcome source of heterogeneity, such differences may also be due to the differential application of eligibility criteria, which is an undesirable source of heterogeneity [12]. Indeed, in a cluster randomised trial, such a phenomenon would be a source of bias because of differences in characteristics of included participants between the groups being compared; in an individually randomised trial, this situation may induce a centre effect, which would not be due to the intervention but rather to differences in following the trial procedures.

Trial planning: relax patient selection criteria

A pragmatic trial aims to recruit patients from an available population who are as similar as possible to the target population. This target population corresponds to the population that would receive the study intervention once it has been shown to be effective and scaled up in the usual healthcare setting. Eligibility criteria should not exclude patients who are less likely to respond to the treatment or those not likely to complete the follow-up. Success in representing the target population in the patients recruited for the trial contributes to the applicability of the trial’s results [13] to the target population. Inclusion and exclusion criteria are often more restrictive in trials of drug interventions than those assessing devices, surgery or other complex interventions; they are also more restrictive in industry-sponsored versus public agency-funded trials [14]. As an example, the TiME trial [15] had very few selection criteria for patients, thus promising very good applicability, besides the fact that it limited the risk of identification and recruitment bias (Table 5).

Table 5 TiME: increased haemodialysis duration session

Trial planning: account for pragmatic features in sample size calculation

Even though sample size formulae may be the same, the reasoning about sample size differs in pragmatic and explanatory trials. First, intervention effects are expected to be smaller in pragmatic than explanatory trials, in part because of the inclusion of patients with a wider range of characteristics, for example those with comorbidities, who are less adherent, and/or who have both less severe conditions, and thus benefit less, as well as those whose condition is more severe and possibly intractable. Other features that might promote homogeneity and thus apparently greater effect sizes in explanatory trials include selecting caregivers and centres based on volume and experience [16]. Second, sample size parameters need to be carefully and realistically specified. A priori specifying a standard deviation that is lower than the post hoc estimate is a common problem [17] and results in optimistic sample size estimates and risks of insufficient statistical power. Therefore, attention should be paid to whether standard deviation estimates are derived from previously conducted explanatory trials—and therefore likely to be too low—or from administrative routinely collected data, for instance, which should adequately capture real-world heterogeneity.

Trial planning: stratify randomisation

A centre effect is to be expected in a pragmatic trial because of centre and participant heterogeneity, as previously discussed. The intervention delivery may also be tailored to the centre context, and such heterogeneity, which, in our opinion, should be welcomed because interventions are applied with heterogeneity in real practice, also contributes to a centre effect. Accordingly, to prevent imbalance between arms and improve power, individually randomised multicentre pragmatic trials should stratify randomisation on centre [18] (e.g. NUTRIREA-2 trial, Table 3). Prognostic factors may also be considered as stratification variables (e.g. ALIC4E trial [19], Table 6), notably when the sample size is small, thus limiting the risk of baseline imbalances [20]. Similarly, for cluster randomised trials, restricted randomisation such as, for instance, stratified randomisation or randomisation by minimisation, is advisable to limit chance imbalances (e.g. IRIS and TiME trials, Tables 4 and 5) [5].

Table 6 ALIC4E: oseltamivir in patients with influenza-like illness

Trial analysis: adjust on stratifying variables, notably centres (e.g. IRIS trial, Table 4)

Although not specific to pragmatic trials, unadjusted analyses of trials using stratified randomisation raise two issues. First, there is inconsistency if factors used to stratify randomisation are not taken into account when analysing the results. Second, ignoring stratification factors in the analysis leads to over-estimated standard errors, wider confidence intervals, inflated p-values and diminished power [21]. Although this is true for any randomised trial, it is a particular concern in pragmatic trials in which between-centre heterogeneity is expected to be higher, as discussed above. Accounting for centre effects is therefore advisable ant it has been shown that random-effects models offer better properties than fixed-effects models [21].

Trial analysis: limit subgroup analyses to those that inform decision-making

Subgroup analyses aim to identify interactions between treatment and pre-specified patient or centre characteristics [22]. Because pragmatic trials aim at informing decision-making rather than promoting an understanding of the mechanism of action, subgroup analyses should only be done if the same subgroups are meaningfully part of usual clinical care or policy decision-making, which requires that the distinction between these subgroups is readily accessible to clinicians (e.g. age, blood pressure), (e.g. APTS trial [23], Table 7) or policy-makers (e.g. subgroups defined by equality, diversity, and inclusion groups.

Table 7 APTS: Delayed cord clamping

Intervention and control groups

Trial planning: permit some tailoring of the intervention

Although heterogeneity in the delivery of interventions is an undesirable feature of an explanatory trial (in which interventions must be standardised), in pragmatic trials, as in future usual care in the target settings, interventions may well be tailored to individual patient needs or the local context in which care is provided [24], especially for complex interventions [25] (e.g. OPERA Trial [26], Table 8).

Table 8 OPERA: physical activity to prevent depression in residential homes

Hawe et al. refer to standardisation by function as compared with standardisation by form (e.g. rather than using a common information kit, how information is provided may differ among centres while the function of the information remains constant across centres), acknowledging that mechanisms that are assessed (i.e. the very components of the intervention) can take different forms from one context to another [25]. Nevertheless, the core components of an intervention need to be specified [27]; otherwise, the interpretation of the results may be complex because one would not know what intervention is being evaluated.

Tailored interventions may contribute to a centre effect [18] or even a provider effect [28], but depending on the research question and trial intention, flexibility in interventions is relatively unproblematic as long as in the trial interventions are delivered by providers in a similar range of ways and in settings that match the target clinical settings. Doing so will introduce desirable heterogeneity in participant outcomes because it mimics reality in that interventions are rarely perfectly standardised in usual care.

Monitoring the extent of tailoring as well as co-interventions raises a further dilemma. On one hand, we want to better understand what actually happened, and this knowledge may help to scale up the intervention after the study has demonstrated benefit. This is the very aim of a process analysis, which is both desirable and recommended [29] (e.g. OPERA Trial, Table 8). On the other hand, any intrusive data collection is undesirable, because it may distort usual clinical practice and patient response. Indeed, patient and health provider behaviour should not be altered outside of the provision of the intervention, to limit as much as possible a Hawthorne effect [30]. Ideally, process measures and outcome assessments should be as unobtrusive as possible, perhaps obtained using administrative or electronic medical record data whose collection is part of the usual care.

Trial planning: ensure that the control intervention reflects usual care

Control interventions are typically non-protocolised usual care or, in comparative effectiveness research, another already widely used active treatment. The use of a usual-care control has several consequences. First, the control can be “no treatment,” but it should rarely be a placebo [31] because placebos are not used in usual clinical care outside of trial contexts. This unnatural comparison group may alter the results of the trial in unknowable ways. Moreover, a placebo control could contribute to an unnatural and undesirable homogeneity among patients allocated to the control group, by reducing recourse to self-prescription with medicines or other treatment modalities (e.g. ALIC4E trial, Table 6). It may also affect outcome assessment, which raises other issues, notably related to the risk of detection bias (cf. Outcome section). We acknowledge that not using a placebo may be a challenging issue for a regulatory agency and therefore, if relevant, encourage trialists to have preliminary discussions with these agencies to justify the need for avoiding placebos. Second, there may be different approaches to usual care in different centres of the target setting. This situation may be accommodated by more than one control group or a single control group that permits unrestricted implementation of a variety of different treatments used in routine care and thus averages out all the kinds of usual care provided [32]. Third, a usual care control means that we expect patients and providers to behave as they would outside a trial context. However, for both patients and providers, behaviours can be altered by trial enrolment, known as the Hawthorne effect [30]. Changes in patient and provider behaviours may affect patient outcome heterogeneity, probably by reducing it. This raises an unsolvable conundrum: except in rare situations, which must be approved by an ethics committee, both patients and providers must be informed that they are involved in a randomised controlled trial. This information procedure is a mainstay of ethical clinical research but may alter behaviours as compared with usual, unobserved, non-trial care. This situation is a strong argument for incorporating consent procedures in the flow of care [33], minimising the obtrusiveness of intervention and data collection in order to minimise participant awareness of the trial and thus minimise the Hawthorne effect.

Trial planning: consider the impact of compliance on sample size

Lack of compliance is common outside a trial context. Sample size calculation should take into account usual-care levels of compliance [34] (e.g. APTS trial, Table 7). Moreover, in pragmatic trials comparing usual-care interventions without blinding, patients from one group may sometimes be easily able to access another study group intervention, which may result in contamination. If this contamination is symmetrical between arms, then it increases variability and decreases the effect size estimate. If this contamination is not symmetrical between arms, which is the most plausible situation, it creates a bias, which can attenuate or exaggerate the effect size estimate. In both situations, the issue cannot be dealt with merely by increasing the sample size. Cluster randomisation may limit contamination, but it may also induce bias arising from the identification or recruitment of individual participants if this processes happen after randomisation [35]. This could be a worse problem than group contamination in the individually randomised version of that trial [36].

Study conduct: do not enforce compliance

In explanatory clinical trials, compliance with intervention and control protocols by both providers and patients is enhanced by trial monitoring often followed by direct contact between a research assistant and the non-compliant patient or provider [37]. However, in pragmatic trials, efforts to promote compliance are undesirable unless such efforts are viewed as part of the intervention itself and would be scaled up in usual practice. The guiding principle is that outside of the study intervention—which should be provided similar to how it would be provided in future usual care should it be shown to be effective in this trial—other behaviours of providers and patients should be unaltered. Trial monitoring is deeply ingrained in the minds of both researchers and study sponsors and setting it aside when performing a pragmatic trial requires a paradigm change. Thus, in pragmatic trials, compliance should not be enhanced but rather considered an outcome and assessed unobtrusively [4]. In the TiME trial (Table 5), although the stated goal of pragmatism had been impaired owing to efforts made to enhance adherence and assess compliance, compliance turned out to be of major interest. Indeed, intervention fidelity was so poor that any difference between groups in haemodialysis session duration (the intervention assessed) vanished over time, which led authors to discontinue the trial.

Study conduct: allow co-interventions

Co-interventions, defined as additional treatments that are not part of the assessed intervention, are another source of heterogeneity. In an explanatory trial, possible co-interventions are listed in the study protocol; some of these may be allowed, but others are prohibited. In a pragmatic trial, co-interventions are not generally considered protocol violations: they are left to the discretion of patients and providers in the trial because this flexibility would apply to usual care in the target setting, once the intervention is in widespread use, and where similar co-interventions will be in use. Measuring them is of interest, but it remains a secondary objective aimed at understanding, and as much as possible, it should be done in an unobtrusive way.

Trial analysis: apply the intent-to-treat principle

Statistical analysis of a superiority trial is expected to be according to intent-to-treat, and this holds true for pragmatic trials [7, 38]. Indeed, per-protocol, completers, on-treatment or complier average causal effect (CACE) analyses aim at understanding what could be observed with optimal compliance and are more suited to explanatory trials [39]. Some argue that per-protocol analyses are of interest if the intervention is expected to be scaled up in settings where adherence to treatment is expected to be better than in the conducted trial [40]. However, this situation casts doubts on the representativeness of the selected settings. One may also argue that per-protocol or CACE analyses are of interest from a patient perspective because they may help patients decide between treatments, though the necessity for perfect compliance to achieve the effects in such analyses needs to be acknowledged. Thus, such analyses should remain secondary analyses.

Missing data is an important issue in intent-to-treat analysis. Missing data may be more prevalent in a pragmatic than explanatory trial in which monitoring is more stringent, except if data are obtained from well-completed medical or administrative registries [41]. Therefore, statistical methods to handle missing data, such as multiple imputation or covariate adjustment, should be used [42] (e.g. ACUDep trial [43], Table 9).

Table 9 ACUDep: acupuncture and counselling for depression

Trial analysis: make sure ancillary studies will not interfere with not imposing specific constraints on patients or physicians

As an ancillary objective of a pragmatic trial, one may seek to better understand the assessed intervention. Thus, at the end of the study, a process analysis “[that] explore[s] the way in which the intervention under study is implemented” [29] may bring a complementary view taking into account contextual issues [44] (e.g. OPERA trial, Table 8). In the same way, per-protocol [40] or CACE analyses may help explain whether lack of treatment effect is due to lack of compliance, whereas subgroup analyses may help identify subgroups of patients who benefit most from the treatment. In a pragmatic trial, all these analyses are generally secondary ones, which means that no specific effort should be made to collect additional data for them if that extra data collection jeopardises the primary purpose of the study, perhaps by distorting the clinical setting and adding extra investigations or disruptive data collection. However, pragmatic trials aim at answering the questions that decision-makers need answered, so one cannot exclude the possibility that subgroup analyses may be part of the primary objective, for example, to investigate aims relevant to health equity.

Outcome

Trial planning: select a routinely collected outcome regarded as important by clinicians and patients

In pragmatic trials, the primary outcome must be directly relevant to patients or the primary stakeholder because it needs to inform decision-making by patients, caregivers and policy-makers [2, 7]. The primary outcome of a pragmatic trial should ideally correspond to an outcome routinely assessed in usual care and is regarded as clinically important and therefore likely to influence providers’ decisions (e.g. TASTE Trial [45], Table 10).

Table 10 TASTE: thrombus aspiration in myocardial infarction

Trial planning: avoid standardisation, blinding and adjudication as much as possible

Outcome assessment raises a conundrum. Some suggest that standardisation (i.e. applying standardised measurement methods), blinding and adjudication should be avoided because they do not correspond to usual practice [7]. Standardisation aims at reducing heterogeneity in outcome assessment, whose consequence is mainly a loss in power. Heterogeneity in outcome assessment also increases the risk of misclassification, which, may be a source of bias [46, 47]. Standardisation may occur for outcomes derived from interviews [48] but also for clinical examinations [49] or even in electronic health records [50]. Blinding and adjudication also aim at reducing the risk of bias (e.g. RESTART Trial [51], Table 11).

Table 11 RESTART: antiplatelet therapy after stroke due to intracerebral haemorrhage

Problems arise mainly for non-objective outcomes. Subjective outcome assessment is indeed known to be potentially influenced by the beliefs, in relation to the treatments, of patients themselves, their caregivers or clinicians [52]. Moreover, in the absence of blinding, this influence may not be the same in the groups being compared. However, another view of this is that these subjective beliefs in relation to the effectiveness of interventions would be active in clinical practice, after the trial has shown one of the tested interventions as more effective and been implemented widely. In that case, the subjective beliefs in the intervention have been well captured in the trial and thus reflect the future usual-care situation accurately. In this quite common situation, eliminating the effect of subjective belief in the trial would eliminate necessary heterogeneity and result in an incorrect estimate of the effect size.

Actually, standardisation, blinding and adjudication do not have the same consequences. Although blinding as well as standardised data collection by researchers may indeed affect patient and care-provider behaviours, adjudication is less problematic because it can be performed after data collection, with blinding to the arm of the patient whose record is being assessed and therefore without bias. However, adjudication, as we most often know, is performed by outside and selected expert clinicians often using information or expertise not available to the clinician in usual care in some future setting. This might produce trial results that differ from results based on usual-care clinician assessments thus reducing the relevance of the trial for decision-making. Although this trial may not be biased (the finding is true for the patients and outcome measures of the trial), it is less applicable to the usual-care situation.

Trial conduct: sensitise data-monitoring committee to the pragmatic nature of the trial

The data monitoring committee is expected to think differently when investigators have clearly articulated their intended goal of pragmatism [50]. The committee should pay more attention to protecting external applicability and avoiding co-interventions delivered by the research team (not the patient and care-provider co-interventions) that are not visible when reading the intervention description in the trial protocol. Depending on the unique circumstances of each trial and intervention being assessed, it may nevertheless keep its original function of monitoring for safety concerns.

Many pragmatic trials, especially of complex non-clinical interventions such as service delivery changes, may not collect data other than at the end of the trial, and so ongoing data monitoring is not relevant because the intervention is low risk. Hence, safety signals are considered unlikely and will not be formally monitored with trial data. This situation may suggest that instead of a data safety or monitoring committee, a more comprehensive trial management committee may be an appropriate supervisory structure, paying more attention to issues such as intervention implementation, patient and centre recruitment, although provision should be made for processes to deal with data confidentially should the need arise during the trial.

If ongoing safety data collection is planned for a pragmatic trial, unobtrusive data sources such as administrative and electronic medical record data may be preferred because they have no effect on the flow of care. However, collecting from these sources may also have substantial time-lags before reliable datasets are assembled and cleaned. Therefore, safety monitoring for acute intervention-related injury, requiring a quick turnaround for action, may have to depend on clinical suspicion. Because intensive safety monitoring may disrupt the usual flow of care, a highly pragmatic design may not be suitable for trials evaluating interventions whose side-effect profile is not yet clear.

Ethical and regulatory issues

Any randomised trial, pragmatic or not, must be conducted in accordance with internationally accepted ethical principles and regulatory guidelines. The very aim of such principles is to protect the autonomy and welfare interests of the participants in clinical trials, and the need for protection is not debatable given horrendous and inhumane “research” such as the Nazi medical experiments and the Tuskegee syphilis study that litter the history of medical research [53]. Participant autonomy is protected by informed consent procedures. With this process, participants voluntarily agree to have a follow-up specific to the study, to potentially experience risk, and to have personal and potentially sensitive data used for the research. Additional protections may be required for people who are particularly vulnerable to potential risks (e.g. children, prisoners or pregnant women, even though there may be no known clinical reason for doing so [54]) and also people with diminished autonomy (e.g. children or adults lacking decision-making capacity).

Patients who refuse to participate in trials may differ from those who agree to enrol (e.g. the Beaver et al. trial [55], Table 12).

Table 12 Telephone follow-up after treatment for breast cancer

In the end, excluding potential participants because of lack of consent may lead to a situation in which the risk profile of included participants may differ from the risk profile of those who were excluded. This situation may reduce heterogeneity among participants, and therefore, the representativeness of the included participants and the applicability of the trial. As a consequence, the challenge in maintaining heterogeneous participants and providers and settings in pragmatic trials may require that trial designers collaborate with ethicists and research ethics committees to obtain a proper balance between protecting research participants while promoting the applicability of the trial findings, although ethical issues must prevail over scientific ones.

Heterogeneity may also be induced by differences in requirements from different research ethics committees, which is an undesirable type of heterogeneity [56] (e.g. PADIT Trial [57], Table 13). Indeed, in such a situation, a patient could be considered eligible and included in some centres but not in others. Such a situation has some similarities with one in which selection criteria would not be applied in the same way among centres, which, as previously discussed, is a source of undesirable heterogeneity. In some countries, centralised research ethics committees can provide a single review covering all participating centres, thus improving consistency and reducing unwanted between-centre heterogeneity.

Table 13 PADIT: prevention of arrhythmia device infection

Trial planning: inclusion of vulnerable patients and informed consent

Although vulnerable patients, including those with co-morbidities, are commonly excluded in explanatory trials, a more inclusive approach may be adopted in pragmatic trials, provided adequate protections are in place. For patients with co-morbidities, protections may include flexibility in administration of the study intervention to meet individual patient needs (e.g. dose reduction) and additional clinically indicated follow-up visits. When patients have diminished capacity to provide consent, a surrogate decision-maker may be required. This may also be the case for emergency research such as trials conducted in intensive care units.

Written informed consent for trial participation is standard for explanatory trials. Pragmatic trials are commonly conducted in primary care settings and usually involve routine medical interventions. Although the ethical principle of respect for persons requires that the autonomy of participants be respected, a more clinical approach to consent in pragmatic trials may achieve the same goal with less intrusion (and thus less propensity to increase homogeneity). Kim et al. [33] describe one such clinical approach to consent called “integrated consent”, whereby informed consent to participation in a pragmatic trial is sought by the health provider in the clinic, during the usual course of care delivery. The health provider discloses key features of study participation verbally and records the patient’s consent or refusal in the electronic health record. In a cluster randomised trial, when the study intervention is a cluster-level intervention (thus, indivisible at the level of the individual) and poses only minimal risk to participants, research ethics committees may grant a waiver of consent when the science would be compromised by seeking consent [58].

Conclusion

Heterogeneity is a prevalent feature of all trials and may be more marked in pragmatic trials, which are expected to closely emulate the target settings. Between-patient variability is probably the main source of heterogeneity. However, there are many other sources of heterogeneity. Some are undesirable and therefore should be limited, but the pragmatic trial should be considered a “dress rehearsal” for the intervention to be scaled up at the end of the trial [59]; therefore, ideally, no restrictions should be added to the trial that will not be carried through to usual care once the intervention has been evaluated. Thus, trial planning and conduct should minimise the impact on behaviours of patients, care providers and outcome assessors. In the end, heterogeneity must be considered and accommodated in the planning, conduct and analysis of a trial.

The arguments developed in the present paper represent the opinions of the authors and are not based on original material or systematic reviews. However, all authors are familiar with randomised trials: they all have been involved in many randomised trials and have conducted methodological work in this field. Therefore, these recommendations rely on personal experiences to date, and we acknowledge that they will need to be updated as knowledge of pragmatic approaches to randomised trials evolves. Indeed, pragmatic trials have received much attention over the last years, although the seminal paper was published more than 50 years ago. Finally, although trials have long been viewed as pragmatic or not, even this original paper described the situation as more complex. The overall intention of the trial designers can fairly be described as either pragmatic (to produce information for decision-making) or explanatory (to clarify an understanding of the mechanisms of action of an intervention), but most trialists now agree that there exist several domains relating to the design choices within the trial and that pragmatism should be viewed as a continuum rather than a dichotomous feature within each domain [7, 31, 60]. The appropriate design approach for each domain should aim at matching the overall intention while optimising the balance between wanted and unwanted heterogeneity.

Availability of data and materials

No data were collected.

References

  1. Higgins J. Cochrane handbook for systematic reviews of interventions. Chichester and Hoboken: Wiley-Blackwell; 2008.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  2. Schwartz D, Lellouch J. Explanatory and pragmatic attitudes in therapeutical trials. J Chronic Dis. 1967;20:637–48.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  3. Zuidgeest MGP, Goetz I, Groenwold RHH, Irving E, van Thiel GJMW, Grobbee DE, et al. Series: pragmatic trials and real world evidence: paper 1. Introduction. J Clin Epidemiol. 2017;88:7–13.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  4. Godwin M, Ruhland L, Casson I, MacDonald S, Delva D, Birtwhistle R, et al. Pragmatic controlled clinical trials in primary care: the struggle between external and internal validity. BMC Med Res Methodol. 2003;3:28.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  5. Donner A. Design and analysis of cluster randomization trials in health research. London: Arnold; 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Robinson KA, Saldanha IJ, McKoy NA. Development of a framework to identify research gaps from systematic reviews. J Clin Epidemiol. 2011;64:1325–30.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  7. Loudon K, Treweek S, Sullivan F, Donnan P, Thorpe KE, Zwarenstein M. The PRECIS-2 tool: designing trials that are fit for purpose. BMJ. 2015;350:h2147.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  8. Reignier J, Boisramé-Helms J, Brisard L, Lascarrou J-B, Ait Hssain A, Anguel N, et al. Enteral versus parenteral early nutrition in ventilated adults with shock: a randomised, controlled, multicentre, open-label, parallel-group study (NUTRIREA-2). Lancet Lond Engl. 2018;391:133–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Feder G, Davies RA, Baird K, Dunne D, Eldridge S, Griffiths C, et al. Identification and referral to improve safety (IRIS) of women experiencing domestic violence with a primary care training and support programme: a cluster randomised controlled trial. Lancet Lond Engl. 2011;378:1788–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Eldridge SM, Ashby D, Kerry S. Sample size for cluster randomized trials: effect of coefficient of variation of cluster size and analysis method. Int J Epidemiol. 2006;35:1292–300.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  11. Lamont EB, Landrum MB, Keating NL, Archer L, Lan L, Strauss GM, et al. Differences in clinical trial patient attributes and outcomes according to enrollment setting. J Clin Oncol Off J Am Soc Clin Oncol. 2010;28:215–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Gentry KR, Arnup SJ, Disma N, Dorris L, de Graaff JC, Hunyady A, et al. Enrollment challenges in multicenter, international studies: the example of the GAS trial. Paediatr Anaesth. 2019;29:51–8.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  13. Jüni P, Altman DG, Egger M. Systematic reviews in health care: assessing the quality of controlled clinical trials. BMJ. 2001;323:42–6.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  14. Van Spall HGC, Toren A, Kiss A, Fowler RA. Eligibility criteria of randomized controlled trials published in high-impact general medical journals: a systematic sampling review. JAMA. 2007;297:1233–40.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  15. Dember LM, Lacson E, Brunelli SM, Hsu JY, Cheung AK, Daugirdas JT, et al. The TiME trial: a fully embedded, cluster-randomized, pragmatic trial of hemodialysis session duration. J Am Soc Nephrol JASN. 2019;30:890–903.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  16. Loudon K, Zwarenstein M, Sullivan F, Donnan P, Treweek S. Making clinical trials more relevant: improving and validating the PRECIS tool for matching trial design decisions to trial purpose. Trials. 2013;14:115.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  17. Vickers AJ. Underpowering in randomized trials reporting a sample size calculation. J Clin Epidemiol. 2003;56:717–20.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  18. Localio AR, Berlin JA, Ten Have TR, Kimmel SE. Adjustments for center in multicenter studies: an overview. Ann Intern Med. 2001;135:112–23.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  19. Butler CC, van der Velden AW, Bongard E, Saville BR, Holmes J, Coenen S, et al. Oseltamivir plus usual care versus usual care for influenza-like illness in primary care: an open-label, pragmatic, randomised controlled trial. Lancet Lond Engl. 2019. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(19)32982-4.

  20. Kernan WN, Viscoli CM, Makuch RW, Brass LM, Horwitz RI. Stratified randomization for clinical trials. J Clin Epidemiol. 1999;52:19–26.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  21. Kahan BC, Morris TP. Improper analysis of trials randomised using stratified blocks or minimisation. Stat Med. 2012;31:328–40.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  22. Rothwell PM. Treating individuals 2. Subgroup analysis in randomised controlled trials: importance, indications, and interpretation. Lancet Lond Engl. 2005;365:176–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Tarnow-Mordi W, Morris J, Kirby A, Robledo K, Askie L, Brown R, et al. Delayed versus immediate cord clamping in preterm infants. N Engl J Med. 2017;377:2445–55.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  24. Baker R, Camosso-Stefinovic J, Gillies C, Shaw EJ, Cheater F, Flottorp S, et al. Tailored interventions to address determinants of practice. Cochrane Database Syst Rev. 2015;2015(4):CD005470.

  25. Hawe P, Shiell A, Riley T. Complex interventions: how “out of control” can a randomised controlled trial be? BMJ. 2004;328:1561–3.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  26. Underwood M, Lamb SE, Eldridge S, Sheehan B, Slowther A, Spencer A, et al. Exercise for depression in care home residents: a randomised controlled trial with cost-effectiveness analysis (OPERA). Health Technol Assess Winch Engl. 2013;17:1–281.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  27. Hoffmann TC, Glasziou PP, Boutron I, Milne R, Perera R, Moher D, et al. Better reporting of interventions: template for intervention description and replication (TIDieR) checklist and guide. BMJ. 2014;348:g1687.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  28. Roberts C, Roberts SA. Design and analysis of clinical trials with clustering effects due to treatment. Clin Trials Lond Engl. 2005;2:152–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Craig P, Dieppe P, Macintyre S, Michie S, Nazareth I, Petticrew M. Developing and evaluating complex interventions: the new Medical Research Council guidance. BMJ. 2008;337:a1655.

  30. Sedgwick P, Greenwood N. Understanding the Hawthorne effect. BMJ. 2015;351:h4672.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  31. Dal-Ré R, Janiaud P, Ioannidis JPA. Real-world evidence: how pragmatic are randomized controlled trials labeled as pragmatic? BMC Med. 2018;16:49.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  32. Dawson L, Zarin DA, Emanuel EJ, Friedman LM, Chaudhari B, Goodman SN. Considering usual medical care in clinical trial design. PLoS Med. 2009;6:e1000111.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  33. Kim SYH, Miller FG. Informed consent for pragmatic trials--the integrated consent model. N Engl J Med. 2014;370:769–72.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  34. Sato T. Sample size calculations with compliance information. Stat Med. 2000;19:2689–97.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  35. Eldridge S, Kerry S, Torgerson DJ. Bias in identifying and recruiting participants in cluster randomised trials: what can be done? BMJ. 2009;339:b4006.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  36. Torgerson DJ. Contamination in trials: is cluster randomisation the answer? BMJ. 2001;322:355–7.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  37. International Conference on Harmonization of technical requirements for registration of pharmaceuticals for human use. Guideline for Good Clinical Practice - E6(R1). https://database.ich.org/sites/default/files/E6_R2_Addendum.pdf.

  38. Zwarenstein M, Treweek S, Gagnier JJ, Altman DG, Tunis S, Haynes B, et al. Improving the reporting of pragmatic trials: an extension of the CONSORT statement. BMJ. 2008;337:a2390.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  39. Hewitt CE, Torgerson DJ, Miles JNV. Is there another way to take account of noncompliance in randomized controlled trials? CMAJ Can Med Assoc J J Assoc Medicale Can. 2006;175:347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Hernán MA, Robins JM. Per-protocol analyses of pragmatic trials. N Engl J Med. 2017;377:1391–8.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  41. Meinecke A-K, Welsing P, Kafatos G, Burke D, Trelle S, Kubin M, et al. Series: pragmatic trials and real world evidence: paper 8. Data collection and management. J Clin Epidemiol. 2017;91:13–22.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  42. Sterne JAC, White IR, Carlin JB, Spratt M, Royston P, Kenward MG, et al. Multiple imputation for missing data in epidemiological and clinical research: potential and pitfalls. BMJ. 2009;338:b2393.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  43. MacPherson H, Richmond S, Bland M, Brealey S, Gabe R, Hopton A, et al. Acupuncture and counselling for depression in primary care: a randomised controlled trial. PLoS Med. 2013;10:e1001518.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  44. Moore GF, Audrey S, Barker M, Bond L, Bonell C, Hardeman W, et al. Process evaluation of complex interventions: Medical Research Council guidance. BMJ. 2015;350:h1258.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  45. Fröbert O, Lagerqvist B, Olivecrona GK, Omerovic E, Gudnason T, Maeng M, et al. Thrombus aspiration during ST-segment elevation myocardial infarction. N Engl J Med. 2013;369:1587–97.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  46. Kahan BC, Feagan B, Jairath V. A comparison of approaches for adjudicating outcomes in clinical trials. Trials. 2017;18:266.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  47. Welsing PM, Oude Rengerink K, Collier S, Eckert L, van Smeden M, Ciaglia A, et al. Series: pragmatic trials and real world evidence: paper 6. Outcome measures in the real world. J Clin Epidemiol. 2017;90:99–107.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  48. O’Muircheartaigh C, Campanelli P. The relative impact of interviewer effects and sample design effects on survey precision. J R Stat Soc Ser A Stat Soc. 1998;161:63–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  49. Kramer MS, Martin RM, Sterne JAC, Shapiro S, Dahhou M, Platt RW. The double jeopardy of clustered measurement and cluster randomisation. BMJ. 2009;339:b2900.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  50. Ellenberg SS, Culbertson R, Gillen DL, Goodman S, Schrandt S, Zirkle M. Data monitoring committees for pragmatic clinical trials. Clin Trials Lond Engl. 2015;12:530–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  51. RESTART Collaboration. Effects of antiplatelet therapy after stroke due to intracerebral haemorrhage (RESTART): a randomised, open-label trial. Lancet Lond Engl. 2019;393:2613–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  52. Savović J, Jones HE, Altman DG, Harris RJ, Jüni P, Pildal J, et al. Influence of reported study design characteristics on intervention effect estimates from randomized, controlled trials. Ann Intern Med. 2012;157:429–38.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  53. Vollmann J, Winau R. Informed consent in human experimentation before the Nuremberg code. BMJ. 1996;313:1445–9.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  54. Macklin R. Enrolling pregnant women in biomedical research. Lancet Lond Engl. 2010;375:632–3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  55. Beaver K, Tysver-Robinson D, Campbell M, Twomey M, Williamson S, Hindley A, et al. Comparing hospital and telephone follow-up after treatment for breast cancer: randomised equivalence trial. BMJ. 2009;338:a3147.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  56. De Smit E, Kearns LS, Clarke L, Dick J, Hill CL, Hewitt AW. Heterogeneity of human research ethics committees and research governance offices across Australia: an observational study. Australas Med J. 2016;9:33–9.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  57. Krahn AD, Longtin Y, Philippon F, Birnie DH, Manlucu J, Angaran P, et al. Prevention of arrhythmia device infection trial: the PADIT trial. J Am Coll Cardiol. 2018;72:3098–109.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  58. Weijer C, Grimshaw JM, Eccles MP, McRae AD, White A, Brehaut JC, et al. The Ottawa statement on the ethical design and conduct of cluster randomized trials. PLoS Med. 2012;9:e1001346.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  59. Schwartz J, Flamant R, Lellouch J. L’Essai thérapeutique chez l’homme. Paris: Editions Médicales Flammarion; 1970.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Taljaard M, Nicholls SG, Howie AH, Nix HP, Carroll K, Moon PM, et al. An analysis of published trials found that current use of pragmatic trial labels is uninformative. J Clin Epidemiol. 2022;151:113-21.

Download references

Acknowledgements

No acknowledgement.

Funding

This work (BG, SEM, CW, MZ, BG) was supported by the Canadian Institutes of Health Research through the Project Grant competition (competitive, peer-reviewed), award number PJT-153045. MT is supported by the National Institute of Aging (NIA) of the National Institutes of Health under Award Number U54AG063546, which funds NIA Imbedded Pragmatic Alzheimer’s Disease and AD-Related Dementias Clinical Trials Collaboratory (NIA IMPACT Collaboratory). The content is solely the responsibility of the authors and does not necessarily represent the official views of the National Institutes of Health. The funder played no role in the study. The funders had no role in the study design; in the collection, analysis and interpretation of data; in the writing of the report; and in the decision to submit the article for publication.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

BG and MT wrote the first draft. All authors critically revised the draft for important intellectual content and gave final approval of the version to be published. BG is the guarantor for the study.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Bruno Giraudeau.

Ethics declarations

Ethics approval and consent to participate

Not required.

Consent for publication

Not required.

Competing interests

All authors have completed the ICMJ uniform disclosure form at www.icmje.org/coi_disclosure.pdf (available on request from the corresponding author) and declare that they have no relevant interests to declare.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article's Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article's Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/. The Creative Commons Public Domain Dedication waiver (http://creativecommons.org/publicdomain/zero/1.0/) applies to the data made available in this article, unless otherwise stated in a credit line to the data.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Giraudeau, B., Caille, A., Eldridge, S.M. et al. Heterogeneity in pragmatic randomised trials: sources and management. BMC Med 20, 372 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1186/s12916-022-02569-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1186/s12916-022-02569-w

Keywords